Hello, I’m Shelley Tremain and I’d like to welcome you to the first installment of Dialogues on Disability, a series of interviews that I am conducting with disabled philosophers and will post here on the third Wednesday of each month. The series is designed to provide a public venue for discussion with disabled philosophers about a range of topics, including their philosophical work on disability, the place of philosophy of disability vis-à-vis the discipline and profession, their experiences of institutional discrimination and personal prejudice in philosophy, in particular, and academia, more generally, resistance to ableism, accessibility, and anti-oppressive pedagogy.
My guest today is Bryce Huebner, an associate professor in the philosophy department at Georgetown University. By his own description, Bryce is a heavily-tattooed philosopher of the biological, cognitive, and social sciences. When he isn’t thinking about philosophy and writing it, Bryce looks for music that he can listen to while he thinks about philosophy and writes it, in addition to making delicious coffees to fuel his academic pursuits. He often goes to punk, noise, metal, hip hop, and dark-wave shows. Over the past few years, he has been learning how to live with the disadvantage that accrues to him because of celiac disease, which is classified as an auto-immune disorder. Bryce, who is ambivalent about conceiving the disadvantage of celiac disease as disability, is happy to discuss this ambivalence, in addition to other issues that arise from his remarks, in the Comment section below this interview.
Welcome, Bryce! To start things off, why don’t you tell us about your background and what motivated you to do graduate work in philosophy and then become a professional philosopher?
Thanks for inviting me, Shelley! I’m excited about your series of Dialogues on Disability and I’m flattered to be your first guest. I think there are many philosophers who will have more interesting things to say about these issues than me, but I’ll do my best to kick things off—at least saying some things about disadvantage and embodiment.
I grew up in a working-class neighborhood in West Valley City, Utah. I did well in school, but academia was never on my radar. I had never heard of philosophy until I got to college. My first semester, I took a class that was team-taught by a philosopher and a historian. I loved it and declared a double major. I didn’t have much of a plan, but I liked being a student. So I asked a historian and a philosopher what graduate school was like. The historian was happy to have done it, but found it intense and difficult. The philosopher told me it was fun and that he’d never been happier. That settled the issue, but I didn’t really know what I was getting into.
I didn’t have the skills or knowledge to go to grad school; and I also didn’t know how to fix that. So, I spent the next year reading as much philosophy as possible, picking up a book whenever I wasn’t unloading freight for UPS. Without guidance, I traipsed across disciplinary boundaries, picking up the books that kept showing up on bookstore shelves. I worked hard, read a lot, and got lucky, ending up in the M.A. program at Colorado State. I still didn’t know what philosophy was. But I worked with amazing people like Jane Kneller, Jim Maffie, and Philip Turetzky. We talked about Marxist and feminist philosophy, Deleuze and Spinoza, the sociology of science, and the exclusion of Africana and Mexica philosophy from the philosophical canon. And I realized that I wanted to be a philosopher. Ten years later, I sort of figured out what philosophers are supposed to do.
You certainly have a rich and variegated philosophical background from which to draw. How would you describe your current work?
My philosophical background helped me to cultivate anti-habitual tendencies. I read widely and organize my writing and teaching to bring multiple perspectives to bear on questions about human agency, as well as the implications of scientific research on ethical theorizing. Right now, I’m approaching these questions with tools from the cognitive and biological sciences, using a theoretical perspective that is informed by my reading of Benedict de Spinoza, Peter Kropotkin, Emma Goldman, Stokely Carmichael, Paulo Friere, Dan Dennett, Kathleen Akins, and some graduate students and early career philosophers who are doing amazing work! For me, philosophy is, and always has been, about remixing!
I’d like to ask you a couple of questions about how you position disability in relation to the philosophy done in some of the areas that you mentioned. Philosophers of disability and disability theorists have identified ways in which aspects central to cognitive science and philosophy of mind rely upon biases and misinformation about disabled people. Has your exposure to this work and to philosophy of disability and disability theory, more generally, altered your own work in the philosophy of cognitive science? If so, how?
This is a hard question to answer. I started reading about disability a couple of years back when I was asked to give a commentary on a cool paper that Joe Stramondo presented at the Central APA. Ever since, I’ve been incorporating disability perspectives into my classes. I have a paper under review that includes a brief discussion of cognitive disability. I’ve also submitted an abstract for a paper on autism and cognitive science with Melanie Yergeau. But I feel like a novice when it comes to questions about disability and I still have a lot to learn. So, I’ll keep reading and teaching work on disability; and I do hope to incorporate research on disability more thoroughly in my writing in the near future. I’ve been thinking, recently, about disability and agency. I hope these thoughts will make their way into my next book. I’m not positive what I want to say and probably won’t be until some time in the middle of my upcoming sabbatical.
I think we’d all love to get a glimpse of your thinking on these matters at this point. So, let me ask you this question: How do you think philosophy of disability can contribute to cognitive science and philosophy of mind, in particular, and philosophy, more generally?
I think it’s much harder to defend depoliticized, un-embodied, and de-worlded approaches to studying minds when you think about disability. Strangely, even the research on embodied cognition has neglected the ways that different kinds of embodiment affect cognition. I’m guilty of that, and I’m working on being better. So I think there are at least two ways that research on disability can and should inform philosophy and cognitive science.
First, research on disability often reveals patterns of entrenched bias in the formation of hypotheses and in decisions about what counts as a signal and what counts as noise. For example, the tacit assumption that cognitive disabilities are deficits makes it easier to treat these disabilities as defects and to design experiments that target the existence and stability of such defects. This perspective obscures the fact that neural differences are the result of biological variation in the human species. This perspective also makes it difficult to consider the ways in which social and material structures contribute to the emergence and stability of observed deficits. Consequently, it’s harder to entertain hypotheses about the full suite of capacities that arise as a result of different forms of embodiment. I think philosophers and cognitive scientists could benefit from thinking about (for example) the impact of things like early intervention and education on Down syndrome and about the results of research on autism carried out by teams with autistic members. These cases promise to open up new hypotheses; and that strikes me as a good thing!
Second, research on disability clarifies the ways in which human action can be scaffolded by, and inhibited by, different material and social environments. This is a fairly obvious point, but I think that it has the potential to reshape the ways that philosophers and scientists approach questions about agency, freedom, and responsibility. Thinking about how the material and social world can increase and decrease the power to act might make some questions look less pressing; but it will also make questions about how to organize our social and material environments far more intriguing, and far more naturalistically tractable. This is where the literature on disability will probably impact my future work, but I’m still not quite sure what I have to say about that.
That’s a great start! Let’s talk about accessibility. Over the past year, you have written posts on Facebook about the problems that arise for you when conference organizers don’t pay attention to the meals that they serve during their conferences. How do you think conference organizers should attend to this issue, and why should they?
I have a hard time conceptualizing celiac disease as a disability—but I don’t know how much that says about me and how much it says about my attitudes regarding disability. Conversations with Megan Dean have been helpful in clarifying my ambivalence on this point. My own experience with celiac has included massive gastrointestinal distress (much of which I would prefer not to discuss), severe cramping, visual migraines, insomnia, mood disorders (including depression and “moodiness”), and serious skin problems. And I will probably experience eating anything that I haven’t cooked myself as risky for the rest of my life. That said, it’s fairly easy to manage; and more importantly, I’ve never been discriminated against for having celiac disease, though I do routinely argue with people who lampoon gluten-free diets. But there are cases where it’s annoying to deal with and there are many social situations in academia that make it a disadvantage. Since there are many others with similar issues (celiac disease, Crohn’s disease, and more), I think it’s important to think about how disadvantages are constructed by failing to account for these forms of embodiment.
Events with food and beer play an important role in the official and unofficial business of academia. Meetings are often accompanied by lunches; department parties often center on food and drinks; meals are sometimes provided at conferences; and meals are frequently a part of giving talks in other departments. When people organize such events, they inquire about dietary restrictions; and, frequently, they claim to understand, but then they fail to organize their events in ways that make them accessible.
Here are a couple of examples. There is an upcoming event where I’ve been told, after several rounds of discussion, that the gluten-free option will involve a whole-wheat tortilla. I’ll bring my own food to that one. At a conference last spring, I provided information about my dietary needs and I was told that food would be available. I asked the conference organizer—several times—to make sure things were taken care of because the conference venue was located far from town. But, when I arrived, there was nothing I could eat. I sat through 11 hours of talks with no access to food and no way to get to my hotel or a grocery store. At multi-day events, things sometimes work out fine on the first day, generating the assumption that things are taken care of—and then, on subsequent days, with no warning, the options disappear. Finally, I don’t think that people understand that a minuscule amount of gluten—such as food cooked on the same surface as a gluten-containing grain—can trigger physical and psychological effects that last for multiple days; and it’s not always possible to determine how things are prepared. This yields a dilemma: go without eating, or eat something and spend several hours wondering if doing so was a mistake.
All of this is annoying, and the added stress and potential for things to go incredibly badly yields patterns of disadvantage. I try to manage this by carrying dried fruits and nuts. I have left conferences to get food, thereby opting out of the ongoing conversation, but this isn’t always possible, especially when I’m traveling, when I lack facility with a local language, or when groceries aren’t easily accessible. Such situations are difficult to navigate, and they could be avoided with a little help from the people who are organizing various events. Academics routinely fail to recognize that people are embodied, and a bit of planning would go a long way toward making academic events more accessible to people with dietary issues. Over the past year, I’ve learned that many people face similar problems. So, I think that the people putting together academic events should think carefully about these sorts of issues, and many other issues that arise as a result of other forms of embodiment, because they can make things more accessible with just a tiny bit more planning.
I want to ask you about your teaching, but let me note, first, that a growing number of philosophers of disability and disability theorists construe disability as socially constituted disadvantage, as systemic, rather than as an acquired, or intrinsic, characteristic of an individual, or property of a person. On this construal of disability, a given person is disabled, rather than has a disability, just as one is gendered, rather than has a gender. On this understanding of disability, the disadvantage to which you have drawn attention is inaccessibility and thus would certainly fall under the rubric of disability. With this understanding in mind, let’s consider the classroom. I think readers of this interview would be interested to know how you incorporate your political sensibility into your pedagogy. What tactics do you use to promote anti-ableist, anti-racist, anti-sexist, anti-oppressive approaches to philosophy in your classroom, on social media, etc.?
One reason why I’ve been ambivalent about calling celiac a disability turns on my understanding of the relationship between embodiment and social disadvantage that you’re calling attention to. Over the past couple of years, I’ve been trying to help my students understand that disability is not an all-or-nothing matter. I have also tried to help them conceive of disabilities as falling within a complex, multidimensional, and socially situated space, by discussing things like anxiety, depression, and celiac disease. One way I’ve done this—which I would like to explore in more detail—is by imagining a space that varies along three dimensions that I’ve already mentioned: first, the typicality of a particular form of embodiment; second, the robustness of the disadvantages that a person experiences as a result of being embodied in a particular way, in a particular environment; and, third, the patterns of socially entrenched discrimination that target that form of embodiment. Along these dimensions, people with celiac are disabled in interesting ways. It is an atypical form of embodiment, but it is fairly common—roughly 1% of the population of the US has celiac disease. It’s disadvantageous in situations like the ones I discussed above, but those situations are a relatively small part of my lived experience, and they are typically easy to manage, though managing them does take quite a bit of time. It doesn’t feel to me like it’s a target of socially entrenched discrimination, though I do have to deal with people who don’t take celiac disease seriously and who assume that I am just avoiding gluten by choice; this is part of what makes eating so risky. Phenomenologically, however, it doesn’t usually feel to me like I’m disabled, though I assume that many people do experience celiac as a disability and I think that they are probably right to do so. Consequently, I believe that thinking of celiac disease as a disability helps to problematize the all-or-nothing view that many people seem to have regarding disabilities and helps to make it clear how relevant the structure of the social world is to the presence or absence of a disability. So, I do talk about my experience with celiac in in my courses.
Beyond that, I don’t really have a general story about how I get students to think about ableism, racism, sexism, and other forms of oppression. I don’t trust myself to be free from bias, so I work hard to listen to and take advice from people who know more than I do. Over the past couple of years, I have been trying to highlight anti-kierarchical and anti-oppressive perspectives in the narratives that I construct for each of my courses. I have been trying to make sure that these perspectives are not just “tacked on” at the end of the course, but are made part of the story that we are constructing together in the classroom. When I lecture, I try to use examples that target issues of disability, race, and class and I try to make it clear that I believe these are important issues to think about in developing ideas about minds, metaphysics, and social practices. I have also started to put together Tumblrs for my classes that draw in discussions of ableism, racism, sexism, classism, colonialism, and more, over the course of the semester. That seems to help the students stay focused on these issues and it keeps me sharing things that I read as I wander through the intertubes. Finally, I tend to crowdsource the process of syllabus design, noting my desire to promote anti-ableist, anti-racist, anti-sexist, anti-oppressive perspectives in my classes. This has yielded a number of really interesting conversations about different parts of philosophy and a lot of excitement among people who would like to restructure their courses, but don’t really know how.
What three or four articles or books have you read recently that you would recommend for this purpose?
I read a ton of different things which makes it difficult for me to pick the stuff that I’ve been the most excited about. So, I’ll just take this opportunity to call attention to a few of the things that I’ve read recently that I think it would be cool for people to pay attention to. One is Melanie Yergeau’s “Clinically Significant Disturbance: On Theorists Who Theorize Theory of Mind,” which appeared in the special issue of Disability Studies Quarterly [ST: vol. 33, no. 4, 2013] devoted to the theme Improving Feminist Philosophy and Theory by Taking Account of Disability; and I would recommend reading that alongside Lisa Zunshine and Ralph James Savarese’s “The Critic as Neurocosmopolite; Or, What Cognitive Approaches to Literature Can Learn from Disability Studies,” which appeared in Narrative, vol. 22, no. 1, in 2014. Lisa Guenther is writing a series of short pieces on the phenomenology of incarceration. Her stuff is amazing, and I would strongly recommend keeping an eye on it, as there is a ton to learn from it. She has written three pieces so far: “Carceral Dreams, Nuclear Afterthoughts”; “A Critical Phenomenology of the Trousdale Turner Correctional Facility”; and “Caging as a Collective Praxis of Social Death.” Finally, Leah Smith is writing some truly awesome blog posts about disability at the Center for Disability Rights, Etc. page, under the heading “The Disability Dialogue.” One of her recent posts, entitled “Optional, People or Optional People?,” addresses the use of nondisabled actors to play disabled characters in film and on stage.
Fantastic suggestions, Bryce. Thanks very much for offering them. I’d also like to thank you for taking the time to be interviewed for the inaugural installment of Dialogues on Disability. You’ve been a terrific guest, raising a number of provocative issues.
Readers of this interview are invited to use the Comments section below to discuss the issues that Bryce Huebner has raised, as well as other issues of relevance. Comments will be moderated. Though signed comments are preferred and encouraged, anonymous comments will be permitted.
___________________________
Please join me here again on Wednesday, May 20th at 8 a.m. EST for the second interview in the Dialogues on Disability series and indeed on every third Wednesday of the months ahead. I have a fabulous line-up of interviews in progress. If you would like to nominate someone to be interviewed (self-nominations are welcomed), feel free to write me at s.tremain@yahoo.ca. I prioritize diversity with respect to disability, class, gender, race, institutional status, culture, and sexuality in my selection of interviewees and my scheduling of interviews.
Thank you Shelley and Bryce! This was very helpful and compelling. I'm convinced. I'll adjust my future conference planning accordingly. (I might need to contact you guys for insight about finer details when it comes time to plan and announce an event's food options).
Bryce: I appreciate you emphasizing the centrality of food and alcohol to academic culture. You've done well to capture one way that this feature of academic culture, if not handled carefully, can have bad — even if unintended — consequences.
Posted by: Nick Byrd | 04/15/2015 at 09:13 AM
Nice interview! Lots of useful ideas here.
How do you go about crowd- sourcing a syllabus?
Tony
Posted by: Tony | 04/15/2015 at 09:14 AM
Thanks again, Nick! And yeah, planning on these things can be sort of difficult!
Tony, my standard go-to is to initiate a Facebook comments thread on a syllabus idea or a draft syllabus. I am also fortunate to have many friends that know a whole lot more than I do about disability, anti-racist theory, feminist philosophy, Indian philosophy, Mexica philosophy, and African and Africana philosophy. So I often ask them what to use in a particular class. Once I post my initial draft, I often get a lot of suggestions, and a lot of recommendations for things that I would have never thought about, given my own biases and my own history. So I incorporate, revise, and often solicit suggestions a second time. So far, it's worked beautifully, and I intend to keep doing it!
Posted by: Bryce | 04/15/2015 at 09:28 AM
Bryce, thank you for sharing your experiences and insights! I was especially struck by how you turned your own ambivalence about celiac disease as a disability into an advantage in terms of problematizing the polarity between disabled/non-disabled.
Posted by: Anne Collins Smith | 04/15/2015 at 10:51 AM
What a fantastic interview! I think conceptualizing something like Celiac Disease through the lens of disability theory can not only enrich our understanding of that sort of embodiment, but it can also expand, adjust, and sharpen the tools that are used by disability theory itself in ways that are neglected by more paradigmatic cases!
Posted by: Joe Stramondo | 04/15/2015 at 12:13 PM
Anne and Joe, thanks for the encouraging comments. They both help to bring out some of the things that I really wasn't sure how to say; and they put them in terms that do a much better job than I did.
My thoughts on these two issues are driven my attempt to disrupt essentialist and teleological views of disability, which I think most people fall into, and do so far too easily. When I turn to questions of disability, I often find myself falling into essentialist views, against my better judgment. Such views run contrary to my hardcore Darwinian commitments, and they run contrary to my thinking about the socially situated nature of agency and action. So I'm trying hard to disrupt those tendencies. And doing so really does seem to depend on, 'problematizing the polarity between disabled/non-disabled', and remembering that the full suite of human variation is not captured by a focus on 'more paradigmatic cases' of disability.
Your language on that second point, Joe, is something that I've been thinking about a lot, and it's part of the reason I have been playing with the multidimensional model that I sketched out in the interview (I'm not committed to those being the right dimensions, they're just a gesture in the direction of my way of thinking about things). I think that a lot of people (myself included) have an easy time thinking that disability only shows up where the values of all of the relevant dimensions are turned up to 11. And that being non-disabled is a matter of having all of those values set to 0. That's a superweird hunch, but it seems to be pretty pervasive. By thinking in terms of a multidimensional space, I want to highlight the ways that the values of each dimensions can vary independently, in ways that yield different kinds of embodiment, and different kinds of disadvantages. Thinking about things in this way helps me, at least, to conceptualize disability and non-disability as both within the space of ordinary human variation; and this helps me to remember that neither is more 'ontologically primitive' than the other. I really want to think more about how a picture roughly like than can help to get rid of the intuitions that fund problematic ideologies about ability.
I also want to call attention to Eric Schwitzgebel's comment over at his own blog, which highlights the socially situated nature of disability and disadvantage. He's right to note that celiac disease only yields disadvantages against the backdrop of particular cuisines, and that there are many cuisines where the effects of celiac disease do not even arise. Experiencing this was really eye opening for me. When I visited El D.F. last summer, I was able to adopt a much more casual and less managed way of eating, and that yielded a radically different experience than the one that I have come to structure my life around in D.C. Like Eric, I hope that we can take up a similar point of view on other ways of being disabled; I also hope that more people can start to remember that we can change the structure of our world if we want to!
(cf., http://schwitzsplinters.blogspot.com/2015/04/dialogues-on-disability.html ).
Posted by: Bryce | 04/15/2015 at 01:35 PM
My sincere thanks to everyone who has commented on the interview thus far! I am glad that folks are engaging Bryce in discussion about some of the practical issues that arise from his remarks, as well as some of the conceptual and other philosophical questions he raised. Philosophy really ought to catch up to other disciplines in the humanities with respect to theoretical work on disability!
As readers of this blog know, I have posted a few times about universal design (UD) strategies. In response to Nick's remarks above, it might be useful, then, to think about how UD would be implemented in regard to the accessibility requirements to which Bryce has drawn attention. An approach to accessibility for people with certain dietary requirements that takes UD and its benefits seriously would make a (wide) selection of types of food available at an event (during meal-time and coffee-time), appropriately labelled and arranged, including gluten-free food, non-diary items, vegan and vegetarian items, etc.
Posted by: Shelley Tremain | 04/15/2015 at 03:03 PM
Shelley, thanks for calling attention to questions about UD in food availability. This is a point where I'm not really sure what to say, and where thinking about things collaboratively and publicly is likely to be a huge advantage. Here's the thing (which I think holds for every person with celiac disease that I know): I'm not going to eat anything that is out in the open, where there is even a marginal risk of cross contamination. The risks are high, the payoffs are low, and the effects of a wrong judgment are bad. Cross-contamination can happen in preparation, but it can also happen in any space where people might drop crumbs, or tough things with crumb-covered hands. So I just avoid eating when it has even the slightest risk of going badly. I don't know what the right way through that is, and I think that it varies from case to case, but it's another thing to keep in mind...
Posted by: Bryce | 04/15/2015 at 03:39 PM
Bryce, I think that the hazards you describe would be avoided if gluten-free foods were available in their own separate containers. I attended a conference last summer at which this was the approach taken. Admittedly, I didn't speak to anyone who ate the gluten-free food that was available, so I don't know if the way the issue was managed was considered adequate. It was a buffet-style arrangement.
Posted by: Shelley Tremain | 04/15/2015 at 05:57 PM
Shelley, I think that it would also have to be made clear to all of the participants that cross-contamination was an issue, and that they needed to be sensitive to it. I think that if I felt like I could trust the other participants, I would be happy with that. If I didn't I would probably skip the food just to be safe. As one of my colleagues put it (he is also dealing with celiac): "it is not merely an upset stomach or even like a bad case of food poisoning. It is far worse. It can be so debilitating that anyone who has the condition will take what looks to others like rather extraordinary steps to avoid it."
Posted by: Bryce | 04/15/2015 at 06:34 PM
Great interview. Thanks for all these interesting thoughts. I'm interested in the food issue. A social centre I sometimes frequent is attended by people with a range of different ethical positions when it comes to food, and the policy there is to go for the lowest common denominator (vegan). Not sure how that might translate for things like celiac.
Posted by: Komarine | 04/16/2015 at 05:32 AM
thanks for your comment, Komarine. I'd love it if Bryce said more about how he is drawing distinctions between disadvantage, discrimination, and disability (the latter construed in the way I defined it in the interview).
Posted by: Shelley Tremain | 04/16/2015 at 08:50 AM
Kormarine, fortunately it's pretty easy to put things together that are gluten free and vegan. The big changes for me were shifting to corn tortillas and rice rather than bread, and from soy sauce to gluten free tamari.
Shelley, I agree that this is a hard distinction to draw, once you start to treat "disability as socially constituted disadvantage, as systemic, rather than as an acquired, or intrinsic, characteristic of an individual, or property of a person". At least for me, I think that having celiac will always feel like a disadvantage, no matter how the world is organized. There are just so many things that I can't do, and that I would like to do (I would like to be able to eat things that I miss eating, and I would like to be able to enjoy particular kinds of mouth-feel that I will never experience again). I feel similarly about by anomalous color vision, and I think that I have a disadvantage that shows up because I don't see what others see in sunsets or the blooming cheery trees that are currently all over DC (or so I gather). But part of what's interesting to me about celiac is that I experience the things that I cannot eat as a loss of access to experiences that I previously had access to. Intriguingly, I haven't had similar experiences when I have given up various types of food as a matter of choice - in these cases, this didn't feel like a loss because I could always decide to do things different. But when I was forced to give up the vast majority of things that I used to enjoy eating, that felt like a real loss, and I experience it as a disadvantage.
These first personal experiences of disadvantage, however, seem to be at least partially dissociable from the way that others act toward me, and the way that the world is structured to institutionalize patterns of socially discriminatory disadvantage. I think that part of what I am trying to do with that distinction is to note that the things that cause the disadvantages I experience can also be fodder for discrimination. As I noted above, it doesn't feel like celiac is a target of socially entrenched discrimination, though there are plenty of ways in which the structure of my social environment sometimes make it harder for me to move about the world (for the kinds of reasons that Eric Schwitzgebel notes over at his blog). At the end of the day, however, I think that people can decide to take my needs into account, and they can organize the social space in ways that don't put me at risk. That would be much better, structurally speaking, and it would shift the patterns of disadvantage that I experience. But many disadvantages would remain, or so it seems to me now.
I don't know what to make of that, and I don't know whether there are problematic ontological assumptions kicking around in that kind of view. Maybe the problem is that I am just misconstruing the nature of my body, and that my psychology just hasn't caught up with my embodiment. I don't know. I find these sorts of issues philosophically fascinating, and I don't really know what to do with them.
Posted by: Bryce | 04/16/2015 at 10:28 AM
This was a great interview -- and the follow up discussion is really thoughtful and interesting. I wonder, though, if some of Bryce's experiences do have an additional element that could be a more socially entrenched disadvantage.
I have in mind my suspicion that the "gluten free" fad has created a misleading sense in people who don't have celiac that celiac isn't really a big deal. My bet is that the uptake of "I have celiac and need special dietary accommodations" is weaker than it would be if the audience heard the claim for what it is: "if you screw this up, I will be debilitated and sick for a long time." There's no "just eat around it" for celiac.
Posted by: Matt Burstein | 04/16/2015 at 04:30 PM
That's exactly right, Matt. Any time I'm eating in a public space, I'm making a decision in favor of "trust them and hope for the best" or "adopt a highly medicalized stance, and describe the effect of microscopic quantities of gluten on the villi of the small intestine". i learned pretty quickly to pick up signals that indicate carefulness, and I always do a lot of research before I consider eating somewhere or with someone that I don't know to be safe. But I think the general consensus is that the gluten free fad has made things significantly more difficult for people with celiac disease.
Posted by: Bryce Huebner | 04/16/2015 at 05:12 PM
Bryce, I really like your multi-dimensional, socially-sensitive conception of disability.
One interesting implication for this conception is, I think, this will includes many more ways of embodiment as disability (in a good way) than we usually do: For example, being a non-native speaker in a particular language community will satisfy most of the dimensions you mentions and would count as a disability even if such disability is "temporary, situational, or context-dependent".
This certainly captured my experience: I am a non-native English speaker myself and I've felt "disabled" in the English-speaking philosophy community.
Posted by: Anonymous | 04/17/2015 at 07:35 PM
I was thinking of lowest common denominator of dietary requirements as a model for universal design for food. The suggestion was supposed to be an alternative to Shelley's idea as a way to overcome the cross contamination worry.
Posted by: Komarine | 04/18/2015 at 12:55 AM
I really like that way of thinking about it, Komarine! Thanks for clarifying.
7:35, That's an interesting point that I hadn't thought about. Thanks for sharing this phenomenological dimension of being a non-native speaker of English in philosophy. This is part of the reason why I want to keep thinking about this way of conceptualizing things. I think you're right that the view I lay out above does open up space for thinking about many things that people don't typically treat as disabilities as disabling. I think there's a lot of value in that, but I also worry that it misses out on something important (I'm not yet sure what). That's why I'm still ambivalent about thinking of celiac as a disability.
Posted by: Bryce Huebner | 04/18/2015 at 07:52 AM
Anonymous's comment about an expansive conception of disability should be recognizable to readers of Foucault's work. In Foucault's College de France lectures of 1975-76 (published in English in 2003 as _Society Must Be Defended_), Foucault introduced the idea of "a racism against the abnormal," which is a conception of race that encompasses not only people excluded and discriminated against on the basis of skin colour or culture (what is standardly understood as racism and anti-Semitism), but rather anyone who doesn't conform to a white, Nordic norm, including people typically regarded as "disabled." The conception of racism against the abnormal that Foucault was developing would encompass the form of marginalization that Anonymous has identified. In a review of Ladelle McWhorter's fabulous book _Racism and Sexual Oppression: A Genealogy_ (Indiana, 1999) that appeared in Hypatia, I do a much better job of explaining Foucault's idea of a racism against the abnormal than I have done in this comment. The review can be read here: https://www.academia.edu/5834459/Review_of_The_Faces_of_Intellectual_Disability_Philosophical_Reflections_by_Licia_Carlson_and_Racism_and_Sexual_Oppression_in_Anglo-America_A_Genealogy_by_Ladelle_McWhorter
Posted by: Shelley Tremain | 04/18/2015 at 10:00 AM
Though not discussed much in the article, Bryce mentioned an interest in how disability theory affects issues of agency. I think this is a really productive area and I would love to hear more about this, and perhaps see Bryce or others on this blog address how our ideas of agency need to account for disability and vice versa. I don't know what's out there but my sense is that not much (or enough) has been written about this. For example, can addiction be considered a disability? I think that it is covered under the ADA but ONLY IF the person is not currently using an illegal substance. This poses all kind of messy legal and ethical dilemmas. When we talk about behavioral conditions like addiction, where do we draw the line between voluntary and involuntary action, between consequences of self-directed behavior and compulsory behavior, between personal accountability and social discrimination, between impaired embodiment and criminality? I think these questions can be applied to many situations and conditions, but addiction is the one that comes first to mind.
Some of the same issues come up with stuttering and speech impairments, for example. Christopher Eagle, Marc Shell, and Joshua St. Pierre have written insightfully about this. Like celiac disease, I don't think most people think of addiction or speech impairments when they think disability, and both likely fall into that liminal space that makes them trouble the clear-cut disabled/nondisabled divide, while also problematizing easy notions of agency/non-agency.
Posted by: Andrew Sydlik | 05/20/2015 at 11:46 AM
Thanks for this comment, Andrew Sydlik! I can't say that I have worked out thoughts about this issue at this point. I am aiming to teach a grad seminar sometime soon that will bring these sorts of questions into play, building on some of my thoughts about learning-theory, attunement, and the socially situated nature of bias. My hunch is that there has been far too great a focus on questions about rationality and free-will in discussions of agency. But I don't have my preferred alternative developed yet—I think there's a lot to learn from disability theorists, and from race theorists, about what agency and freedom really amount to. Recently, I've learned a lot from a paper that Femi Taiwo (the graduate student at UCLA, not the political philosopher at Cornell) is writing about agency and race. But I can't say that I've digested all of his amazing insights yet!
Posted by: Bryce Huebner | 05/20/2015 at 12:34 PM