Hello, I’m Shelley Tremain and I’d like to welcome you to the fifteenth installment of Dialogues on Disability, the series of interviews that I am conducting with disabled philosophers and post here on the third Wednesday of each month. Dialogues on Disability is designed to provide a public venue for discussion with disabled philosophers about a range of topics, including their philosophical work on disability; the place of philosophy of disability vis-à-vis the discipline and profession; their experiences of institutional discrimination and personal prejudice in philosophy, in particular, and in academia, more generally; resistance to ableism; accessibility; and anti-oppressive pedagogy.
My guest today is Joshua Knobe. Josh is a professor of philosophy and cognitive science at Yale. Most of his research is in experimental philosophy. Though Josh tried his best in this interview to focus on more intellectual topics, what he is really most excited about these days is his five-year-old daughter Zoe.
Welcome to Dialogues on Disability, Josh! For several years after you finished your undergraduate degree, you worked for organizations that address the needs of homeless people and low-income people. Although you were conflicted about returning to academic philosophy, you ultimately did so. Please describe this work and how it has motivated your philosophical interests.
Thanks Shelley! This whole series is a fantastic service, and it's wonderful to have a chance to appear here.
Anyway, by the time I finished up undergrad, I was already pretty hooked on philosophy, but day to day, I worked in homeless shelters trying to figure out how people could get better access to public housing.
To be honest, I never showed any real talent in this kind of work, but I did pursue it with a rather extreme level of devotion. In part, this was due to my boss, John Henneberger, who was a truly inspiring figure. He had this way of making you feel like the project that you were working on at the moment was absolutely the most important thing in the world.
Here is one anecdote that will give you a sense what it was like to work there. The whole time I had that job, John was locked in a conflict with the organization's board of directors. The board insisted that his salary was way too low and that no one could live on so little money; but John obstinately refused to accept a raise. The result was an organization designed to fight poverty in which the director himself was teetering on the brink of poverty! (In a sign that there is some justice in the world, John later went on to win the MacArthur "Genius" Award.)
Like many people that age, I was very uncertain about what I should be doing with my life, but in the end, I decided to leave this kind of work and apply to grad school in philosophy. Just as you say, I felt pretty conflicted about the whole thing. Even after I was officially a graduate student, I spent a lot of time working for my old job. I guess this all left me with an especially bad case of that feeling, which I think plagues a lot of philosophers, that one had really better do something of value to justify one's decision to enter this profession.
I'm sure that this early experience shaped my later work in a number of different respects, but the most salient one is the general sense I developed of what it looks like when one is doing something truly important. In particular, I was struck by the fact that the most important things in life often look awfully humdrum or pedestrian.
People like John Henneberger make such a huge difference in the world, but it is not as though they are always running around making passionate speeches like the heroes in the movies. Much of the time, they are just going through the painstaking work of gradually building a consensus that can lead to real reform. My sense is that things are much the same in philosophy. Sure, there are moments of electrifying insight, and these are the moments that we tend to focus on when we think about the history of our discipline. Yet, my guess is that a lot of the time what really makes the most difference is the hours that we spend doing the more mundane stuff: teaching classes, meeting with students, working on various committees that move things ever so slightly in the right direction.
Please explain the process through which you have produced philosophy and why you use voice-recognition software.
Although I have never considered myself to be disabled, I have a long-standing problem with my hands that makes it very difficult for me to write or type. The problem started when I was in graduate school, and for much of the time that I was there, I was never able to type more than four or five hours a week (including emails, comments on undergrad papers, everything).
As a result, I developed a somewhat odd way of producing philosophy papers. The basic goal was to minimize the total amount of typing required. To do that, I would spend an enormous amount of time just walking around thinking, gradually composing and revising in my head. Then, only after I had figured out precisely what I wanted to say in the paper, would I sit down to actually type it.
If you stop to think about it, the total number of words that you need to type to create a complete philosophy paper actually isn't that large. Almost all of the typing comes from trying to work things out on paper. If you instead work things out by taking long walks, you can go a whole year as a philosopher while typing relatively little. That was the approach I took for most of graduate school.
Then, later, voice-recognition technology improved substantially. For many people, this made things a bit more convenient in one way or another (say, by making it even easier to send texts on an iphone). But, for folks like me, it made a huge difference. At this point, the problems that I have with my hands really don't impact my life too much at all.
I have tended not to mention this whole thing to other people, and when I am honest with myself, I have to admit that I am somehow embarrassed or ashamed of it. I guess that I have the feeling that because the problem is such a minor one, I should be able to just deal with it myself and not make myself a burden to other people. Of course, when I write out the idea explicitly like this, it is clear that it doesn't make any sense: why should the fact that my problem is a minor one mean that I should keep it a secret? In any case, this is the first time that I have spoken about this whole thing so publicly.
I'm sure that there are a bunch of other people in philosophy who face similar difficulties, so I thought it might be helpful for me to pass on one final piece of information. In my experience, the philosophical community has been unfailingly gracious and accommodating. I was worried that people might find it annoying that I wasn't able to do certain things, but on the rare occasions when I have mustered up my courage and asked people for help, the result has always been that people seemed more than happy to give me a hand.
Let’s turn to your landmark research and teaching, Josh. You are widely known as one of the founders of the experimental philosophy movement. In your view, experimental philosophy is frequently misconstrued and mischaracterized. Please tell our readers and listeners what you think experimental philosophy is, what purposes it can serve, and what it has achieved thus far.
I am a bit reluctant to say anything bad about our fellow philosophers, so, let me first emphasize that most of what people say about experimental philosophy is actually very accurate and helpful. In particular, when people engage with specific studies, they almost always describe the studies correctly and often have very useful comments. The trouble only arises when people try to step back and characterize the experimental philosophy movement as a whole.
When people do that, they tend to try to make sense of experimental philosophy against the backdrop of the tradition of analytic philosophy. So people start out with certain concepts or distinctions, drawn from the analytic tradition, and then they try to explain what experimental philosophers are doing within that sort of framework. Among those who take this approach, one of the most common suggestions is that analytic philosophers have a methodology that relies on the use of intuitions and that the principal aim of experimental philosophy is to provide some kind of critique of this methodology.
This is really a grotesque mischaracterization of the field. I recently conducted a quantitative analysis of recent studies in experimental philosophy, and the results indicated that only 1.1% of the studies aimed to show that appeals to intuition are in some way unreliable. In other words, there are indeed some experimental philosophy studies whose aim is to diss on the methods associated with analytic philosophy, but this group of studies makes up only a tiny portion of what experimental philosophers do. Almost all of the studies in experimental philosophy are doing something else.
So then, what are experimental philosophers actually doing? Well, lots of things. It is an extraordinarily diverse movement, knit together only by a commitment to conducting systematic experimental studies, and different experimental philosophy projects have very different aims.
Still, I do think that it is possible to identify one trend that might be especially relevant to readers here: recent work in experimental philosophy has been opening up questions that played very little role in the 20th-century analytic tradition. Just to illustrate, some of my own recent work has been concerned with questions about the psychological processes underlying prejudice against gay people; whether thinking of someone in terms of their body leads to dehumanization; how to understand moral responsibility in cases of implicit bias; and what it means to truly “be yourself” or to attain “true happiness”. In research that I am currently pursuing with Sam Liao and Aaron Meskin, we ask whether the systematic study of punk rock can help to illuminate the concept of art.
My guess is that this is the aspect of experimental philosophy that will prove most directly relevant to people who are interested in issues about discrimination and disadvantage. It seems at least relatively unlikely that the best way for us to move forward on issues in this area will be to engage in even more reflection on the nature of intuition, conceptual analysis, etc. Instead, we might do better just to stop worrying about whether our work connects in any way to the themes of 20th-century analytic philosophy. There is a real need for philosophers who can simply take their expertise—in philosophy of disability, in feminist philosophy, in philosophy of race—and use it to engage in the most straightforward way with the empirical issues that arise in these areas.
You’ve mentioned your work on the self. Many philosophers have written about the “true,” or “authentic,” self. However, you think that these philosophers have misunderstood what ordinary people really mean when they talk about the “true self.” How, in your view, do other philosophers misunderstand ordinary notions of the self and what alternative view do you propose?
Maybe the best way into this issue is to start with a simple example. A few of my friends struggle with drug addiction. It is clear that they experience a real conflict: they have a strong desire to get clean but also have a strong desire to continue using. Yet, looking at this conflict, it is hard to avoid the sense that the two desires are not simply on a par. I can't help but feel that there is some sense in which the desire to get clean comes from their true selves—the people that they really are deep down inside—and that if they give in to the desire to keep using, they will betray their own selves.
The difficulty arises when we try to spell out this intuition more philosophically. Given that these people actually do have both desires, what could it even mean to say that one desire comes from their “true self” and the other desire does not?
The usual way to answer this question relies in some way on the notion of reflection. One starts out with a distinction between some more reflective sort of mental state (reason, second-order desire, valuing) and the various other, less reflective states (immediate impulses, visceral desires). Then one privileges the more reflective states, suggesting that they uniquely express the true self. This approach provides a simple analysis of cases like drug addiction. Perhaps the reason that the desire to keep using is not part of an addict's true self is simply that the addict herself rejects this desire on reflection.
In my view, this approach is deeply mistaken. We do indeed tend to make sense of other people in terms of the notion of a “true self;” but it is no good to try to spell out this ordinary notion in terms of anything about our capacity for reflection.
To explore this issue, we looked at a case that is in some ways structurally similar to the case of drug addiction but is, in other respects, deeply different. Consider an agent who is gay but who believes that homosexuality is morally wrong. He has a desire to be with another man, but he hates this aspect of himself and sincerely wishes that he could rid himself of it. This agent, too, experiences a conflict between two competing desires. So which of the two desires expresses his true self? When he reflects, he completely rejects the desire to be with other men, and the reflection-based view would therefore say that if he were to act on this desire, he would betray his true self. But is that actually the right verdict in this case?
When we looked at this case experimentally, the result we obtained was considerably more complex and, in my view, far more philosophically interesting. Those experimental participants who identified themselves as political conservatives tended to say that the agent’s desire to refrain from having sex with other men expressed his true self, whereas those who identified themselves as political liberals tended to say that this desire was itself a betrayal of the agent's true self.
In short, the overall pattern of intuitions in these cases suggests that the notion of reflection just doesn't play much of a role in our concept of a true self. In the specific case of drug addiction, it happens that the part of the self that we pick out as the true self is also the part that the agent endorses on reflection. Yet, this agreement appears to be merely a coincidence. In other cases, you may find yourself having the intuition that the agent's true self is precisely the aspect of the agent that they would most completely disavow.
As our experimental work continues, it seems to point ever more clearly to a very different picture of people's ordinary notion of a true self. At the core of this picture is the idea that people's true selves call them to do what is good. Sometimes the part of the self that draws us to the good is the more reflective part, sometimes it is the more visceral part, but, this whole reflective/visceral distinction has nothing to do with our ordinary notion of the true self. The ordinary notion is, rather, that the true self is that part of us—whichever it might be—that draws us toward the good.
At present, you are appointed in both the cognitive science program and philosophy department at Yale. Your office is located in the Yale psychology department and you work with psychology students. How do the values of these different academic cultures differ?
It has been fascinating to experience these two quite different cultures up close. The two disciplines differ in numerous ways; and I think that each of them has a lot to learn from the other. I'll focus here on just one difference that strikes me as especially important.
Within philosophy, there is an almost absurd value placed on intelligence. Just imagine what might happen if a philosophy department were faced with a choice between (a) a job candidate who has consistently made valuable contributions in research and teaching and (b) a candidate who has not made any valuable contributions in either of these domains but who is universally believed to be extraordinarily smart. In such a case, I fear that many philosophy departments would actually choose the latter candidate.
In psychology, it is exactly the opposite. When people are trying to decide whether to hire a given candidate, the question is never, “How smart is she?” Instead, the question is always, “What has she actually discovered?” If you haven't contributed anything of value, there is basically no chance at all that you will be hired just for having a high I.Q.
This cultural difference results in a quite radical difference in the atmosphere that one finds in graduate education. Philosophy students experience constant anxiety about whether they are smart enough. Psychology students also experience a lot of anxiety, but it is about a completely different topic. They have this ever-present sense that they absolutely must find some way to make a concrete contribution to the field.
This aspect of our disciplinary culture really serves to shape the character of our everyday interactions. In philosophy, there is so much concern about whether the thing that one is about to say is smart or not smart. As a result, philosophers often self-censor. They feel unable to actually engage with the philosophical question at hand because they are too busy thinking instead about what the things they say will reveal about their intellectual abilities. In psychology, the situation tends to be quite different. The most common concern is not whether the thing that one is about to say is smart or not smart but rather whether it will actually help to make progress on the project.
I think that this is one area in which the culture of philosophy could potentially do with some improvement, but to be honest, I don't have any very good ideas about precisely how we might go about changing things. Of course, the simplest thing that we could do would be to call on individual philosophers to change their behavior. We could say, “When you are working on a philosophical question, don't think about whether what you are saying is smart, or whether it is creative, or whether it shows a mastery of the existing literature. Just think about the philosophical question itself and try to make real progress on it.” Yet, it seems that there is something a bit glib about this response. Given the way things are set up at present, it would take extraordinary courage for an individual philosopher just to spontaneously stop caring about looking smart and start focusing only on making genuine intellectual progress. If we are going to make this sort of individual change possible, it will presumably require some larger change in the incentive structures that govern our discipline as a whole.
One last question: what resources—articles, books, videos, etc.—do you recommend on the topics that you’ve discussed in our interview?
First of all, if you are interested in learning more about experimental philosophy, you are really faced with an embarrassment of riches. There are so many different people doing so many different interesting things on so many different topics that it is a bit hard to know what would be best to mention. So let me just give a quick sampler of some exciting papers from a bunch of different folks on a variety of different topics. You might try looking at a paper on metaphor; one on the underrepresentation of women in philosophy; a formal semantics paper on epistemic modals; an aesthetics paper on exposure to bad art; a metaphysics paper on mereology; or a paper on whether Buddhism allays the fear of death.
If you want to learn how to do some experimental philosophy yourself, I actually don't think that reading more is the key. Instead, the most important thing is probably just to start working with someone who already knows how to run studies. In my experience, experimental philosophers tend to be very supportive and welcoming, so I bet you can find someone in the experimental philosophy community who would be happy to help out. But there is actually no need to confine yourself to the discipline of philosophy in particular. Wherever you are, there are probably plenty of people around who know a whole lot about statistics and experimental design, and I’m sure some of them will be happy to help you out.
Finally, I can't help but recommend my wife Alina Simone's book of essays, You Must Go and Win, the cover of which appears below. It probably won't be terribly relevant to your academic work, but on the plus side, it is fucking hilarious.
[Image description: the book cover has a white background and depicts flames arising from an audio speaker of the sort rock musicians use on stage. The title of the book appears in red, green, blue, and gold capital letters across the top and down the right-hand side of the cover. The author’s name appears in red capital letters at the bottom left of the cover.]
Thanks for these fantastic recommendations, Josh. And thanks for your fascinating and candid remarks throughout this interview. Your interview is a really wonderful addition to the Dialogues on Disability series.
Readers/listeners are invited to use the Comments section below to respond to Joshua Knobe’s remarks, ask questions about experimental philosophy, open a discussion about or offer their expertise on voice-recognition technology, and so on. Comments will be moderated. As always, although signed comments are encouraged and preferred, anonymous comments may be permitted. Many thanks to Thomas Nadelhoffer who generously provided technical assistance in the preparation of this interview.
_________________________________________
Please join me here again on Wednesday, July 20th at 8 a.m. EST for the sixteenth installment of the Dialogues on Disability series and, indeed, on every third Wednesday of the months ahead. I have a fabulous line-up of interviews planned. If you would like to nominate someone to be interviewed (self-nominations are welcomed), please feel free to write me at s.tremain@yahoo.ca. I prioritize diversity with respect to disability, class, race, gender, institutional status, nationality, culture, age, and sexuality in my selection of interviewees and my scheduling of interviews.
Thanks for another fantastic interview, Shelley. You do better than any one else I know at bringing voices together from different parts of the field.
Josh, this is really a great contribution. Thanks for sharing some of your personal story as well as the latest existing work you are doing. I am a big fan of your work on the true self. I wanted to raise one question, which I think is consistent with what you have shown. In your remarks on addiction, you talk about the experience of feeling like one's true self is a self that doesn't have a dependency on the addictive substance (or activity, etc.). I think that many people who deal with addiction do have those thoughts. But I think a lot of people also identify with their addictions, and some also see the use of addictive substances as agentic -- addiction can be a way of coping with various other noxious aspects of life. There are moments in a "recovery" process when one tries to distinguish one's self from the addiction, as well as a lot of stigma and shame that make one see the addiction as bad, risky, and hurtful to others. So we can come to see addiction as alien. But I think a philosophy of the self should also be able to explain how we can come to identify with addiction (even knowing that is it viewed negatively by others). In this respect, addiction can be like mental illness and other disabilities: these are all regarded negatively by others, and all make life challenging in various ways, but some people come to feel that who they are is bound up in potentially positive ways with these aspects of life. I know you have theoretical resources for allowing each of us to decide our own true selves. I think addiction is a domain where attitudes have been so punitive that we need to think more about ways addiction can become part of identity without pre-judging those for whom this is the case.
Posted by: Jesse Prinz | 06/15/2016 at 08:36 AM
Hi Jesse!
So great to see you here. Your own work on people's conceptions of the self has been really inspiring, and definitely did a lot to kick off this whole surge of research on the topic.
Your comment gets at some really important issues in the psychology of addiction, but before I turn to that, just a quick, more superficial point about the relationship to our theory.
In our example about a gay man who believes that homosexuality is morally wrong, many people have the intuition that the agent's desire to refrain from being with other men is getting in the way of the expression of his true self. The theory predicts that people should *not* have this same intuition in the case of addiction, i.e., that people should not think that addicts' desire to refrain from using is getting in the way of the expression of their true self. If people do turn out to have this intuition, that result would provide evidence against our theory.
Now, on to the deeper question. I think you are completely right to say that many people cherish the pain they experience, regarding it as integral to their true selves, and that this can be a serious barrier to treatment. When people are feeling depressed, they sometimes want to feel better, but they also sometimes have the sense that the emotions they are experiencing in that moment are far more real and true than anything they experience when feeling more cheerful. I am sure that many people feel the same way about the emotions that draw them into addiction.
This is an enormously important issue, which we tried to investigate (albeit without much success) and which I hope further research will pursue more seriously.
Posted by: Joshua Knobe | 06/15/2016 at 10:28 AM
Joshua,
Thanks for a great interview. I wanted to pick up on something you said about the folk notion of the true self--namely, that "the true self is that part of us—whichever it might be—that draws us toward the good." If this were right across the board, then it seems like people would be unwilling to attribute a true self to people they deem to be without conscience or irredeemable. So, knaves and psychopaths alike would be lacking a true self. But this doesn't seem right. When people talk about Hitler, for example, they don't reference his being "drawn toward the good," rather, they say he's evil to the core (indeed, perhaps even pure evil). We are also happy to blame these individuals who seem lacking in a drive towards the good. But that, too, is puzzling. For it seems like it is the true self who gets the praise or the blame. But what to do in cases of agents without a true self? Thoughts?
Posted by: Thomas Nadelhoffer | 06/15/2016 at 11:22 AM
Thanks Thomas! You are picking up on a genuine error in the way I formulated that sentence. I should not have said that people always conceive of the true self as the part of the self that is good. Rather, what I should have said is that (a) there is an effect such that when people regard a part of the self as good, they are more inclined to see it as an expression of the true self and (b) this effect explains precisely the intuitions that originally led people to think that the true self has something to do with reflection.
That said, I do think that this effect would arise even for judgments about the agents we regard as most evil. Suppose that Hitler had a brief moment of doubt in which he experienced compassion for the people in the concentration camps and wondered whether he was making a mistake. My guess is that people would not say that in this moment he was betraying his true self. Whatever else they might think about his true self, I would guess that they would see this moment of compassion as a legitimate part of it.
Posted by: Joshua Knobe | 06/15/2016 at 12:28 PM
Hi Josh,
Thanks for this great interview, and also for such interesting work on the true self. I’m wondering if you have any thoughts (or even data) on the possibility that people’s intuitions are sensitive to explanations of why someone feels or judges a particular way in a given case. Here’s an attempt to express what I have in mind:
Consider the study you published (along with Newman and Bloom) concerning homosexual feelings/judgments (Study 3 in the PSPB paper you link to). You found that intuitions about Mark’s true self tracked subjects’ personal views about the morality of homosexuality. People who disapprove of homosexuality are more likely to say that Mark’s true self tracked his anti-homosexual attitudes (beliefs or feelings), whereas the opposite was true of the intuitions of people with opposite views about homosexuality.
I wonder whether these intuitions might be sensitive to explanations of why Mark had the relevant beliefs/feelings about homosexuality. In the vignettes you present in the paper, Mark was either an evangelical Christian or a secular humanist. But what if he was a fundamentalist Muslim or the member of a free-loving cult? Do you think that the explanation why he has the beliefs (or feelings) he does might affect what people consider to be his true self? For instance, do you think that those conservatives in your study would be as likely to say that Mark’s true self believes that homosexuality is wrong if that is due to his identification as a fundamentalist Muslim? In a different version of the vignette, do you think that liberals would be as likely to say that Mark’s true self believes that homosexuality is morally acceptable if this is due to his identification as a member of a cult?
If you don’t think that people’s intuitions would be sensitive to these factors, then I’d be really interested to hear why not. If you do they’d be sensitive to them, then I’d be interested to hear why and also what significance you might take this to have.
Thanks in advance!
Posted by: Ben M-Y | 06/15/2016 at 03:23 PM
Hi Ben,
This is a really nice point. I definitely do get those intuitions, and I think it would be great to pursue these issues further. I would be super curious to hear your own opinions on these phenomena, but first, let me quickly say something about how I would think about this.
Basically, our idea is that people's ordinary notion of a 'true self' is the application of people's general tendency to see things as having essences to the specific case of the self. When one looks outside the case of the self in particular, it seems like one sees exactly the same thing. For example, take the way people think about the United States. Many people think that the United States has all sorts of accidental features that it happened to develop in one way or another but that there is also something like 'the essence of the United States' or 'what the United States is really all about.' Or take the way people think about philosophy papers. Many people think that the typical philosophy paper just happens to have various accidental features that it acquires in one way or another but that there is also something like 'the essence of the paper' or 'what the paper is really all about.' Our thought is that the notion of a true self is just one part of this larger way of thinking. We have a general ability to think of things as having essences, and we can then apply that to a human being ('the essence of Ben,' 'what Ben is really all about').
In our work on this topic, we show that the tendency to think of the good things as particularly expressive of the true self isn't specific to the self but also applies equally to these other things (nations, papers, etc.). I am thinking that your effect would show that same pattern. For example, suppose that the United States had in place some really wonderful law but that this law was the product of lobbying from some special interest group of which we generally disapprove. My guess is that -- just as you suggest for the case of the self -- people would be reluctant to say that this law expressed the essence of the United States. Does that sound right to you?
Posted by: Joshua Knobe | 06/15/2016 at 05:08 PM
Hi Josh,
Thanks for the reply. It's informative to get the bigger picture behind your project and how you're thinking about the true self. To be honest, I had the reaction, initially in response to what you said in the interview about people's true selves being what draws them to the good, that your view sounded quite Platonic. And now in response to the broader picture regarding essences, I'm having this reaction even more strongly. To be clear: this is a good thing in my view! I'm a fan of a, roughly, Platonic conception of the true self. (I borrow the Platonic label from Gary Watson.) This is part of what intrigues me so much about the view you're putting forth.
As for my thoughts about the kinds of cases I brought up in my first comment, I was thinking that maybe the tendency you (and your colleagues) have uncovered is a bit more nuanced than it seems. In broad strokes, we might say that we tend to attribute attitudes to a person's true self that align with what we also take to be good. But I suspect that the tendency is really to attribute attitudes to the person's true self that we agree with *when they were adopted for the right reasons*. The prediction is that a conservative who agrees with the belief that homosexuality is morally wrong will attribute this belief to Mark's true self only when he believes this for what the conservative takes to be good reasons. My thought was that this further condition would be satisfied when Mark is described as an evangelical Christian, but not when he is described as a fundamentalist Muslim (assuming that your subjects are Americans or Westerners).
Of course, this is a testable prediction, and I wonder if anyone has tested it. I haven't. But I think it would be interesting to find out whether the prediction has anything going for it. Thoughts?
Posted by: Ben M-Y | 06/15/2016 at 09:42 PM
Hi again, Josh. Thanks for the interview and the reply. Just a quick clarification. I realize that the theory predicts, that "people should not think that addicts' desire to refrain from using is getting in the way of the expression of their true self." I guess that's what I was resisting. The theory may be right to predict this, but these attitudes that the theory uncovers (a the theoretical decision to compare these to the attitudes towards homophobia) are problematic. Homophobia is a pernicious attitude directed towards others based on false beliefs. Addiction is, in some cases, a self-medicating coping strategy. It can affect others in serious ways, but I think casual use of addiction examples in the same context as homophobia may give the wrong impression. Participants in the studies may treat the two similarly (using the formula: these are bad therefore not part of the true self), but there may also be a normative issue here. Given that the self is a construction, we can ask, what things should we try to eliminate from ourselves, and what things should we keep. It may be that bigotry should always be eliminated, but things may not be so simple with addiction and mental illness. As theoreticians who try to simple give descriptive stories, we sometimes implicitly enter into the normative sphere. By equating the cases, and saying ordinary people see both addiction and homophobia as things that are bad, hence not part of identity, one may be taken as endorsing this stance. I know that you don't endorse this stance. But then the question becomes, are there resources within the theory, to explore the differences. I think the answer you gave about the depression case, and your efforts there, speaks directly to this, so no need to respond. I just wanted to clarify. Thanks again.
Posted by: Jesse Prinz | 06/16/2016 at 08:35 AM
Hi Ben,
I would be really interested in hearing more about how this stuff relates to your own work. What I am suggesting is that people's ordinary concept of the true self has nothing to do with endorsement or with distinction between reason and appetite. I had thought that your own view was pretty much the opposite (i.e., that the concept of the true self was deeply related to endorsement and to the reason/appetite distinction), but in light of your comments here, I am thinking that I was actually mistaken in my understanding of your account. Could you maybe say a little bit more?
Josh
Posted by: Joshua Knobe | 06/16/2016 at 10:16 AM
Hi Jesse,
This is a really valuable point. Clearly, it is not enough just to reach a better understanding of people's ordinary views on these topics (an empirical project); we also need to ask whether these views are problematic in certain respects (a critical project). The specific point you make here is a very important one for that latter question.
In any case, the work we are doing might make some very small contribution to the critical project. Specifically, it seems that a first step in getting at what is most problematic in people's ordinary conception is just to have a clear understanding of what that conception is.
Posted by: Joshua Knobe | 06/16/2016 at 10:26 AM
Josh,
I want to thank you again for an excellent interview. As with the other disabled philosophers I’ve interviewed for this series, I am moved that you entrusted me with your story and your philosophical views.
As I indicated to you as we put the finishing touches on the interview, I want to make some remarks about your thoughts with respect to disability and self-identification. I hope that you will pick up on these should you respond to my comment.
First, let me make a few remarks about your writing process and your use of voice-recognition technology because, when I read your responses to my interview questions and other requests for information, this aspect of your interview affected me most deeply.
Indeed, your remarks about the ways in which you got through grad school cannot not go unremarked on here. For my part, I have been repeatedly awed, saddened (if not angered), and grateful when I have read these remarks in the interview:
(1) I’ve been awed because your remarks are a reminder of how people who, in some way, don’t conform to narrow constructions of the worlds in which they inhabit routinely manage to find ways to thrive in these worlds designed to exclude them. For one thing, I think that (once again) we should ask how much the discipline’s preoccupation with intelligence determines the way in which contributions must be made, who can make them, what form they must take, what modality they must employ, etc.
(2) I’ve been saddened (and even angered) because you seem to have thought that you were not entitled to ask for different evaluation techniques than your peers. Everyone deserves an education that is accessible to them and universities are legally required to deliver it to them.
(3) I’m grateful because you have made it easier for some other reluctant philosopher with less prestige and privilege than you to come forward and ask for what they deserve from their colleagues, from their own institutions, and from the philosophical community at large. Thank you for making a difference in the very way that you yourself describe at one point in the interview.
On the matter of disability and self-identification: I think you should identify as disabled. I also hope that you will begin to read philosophy of disability and disability theory. Anecdotal reports suggest that many people come to identify themselves as disabled after they have read in the area and become informed about the conceptions of disability (and their associations with oppression, disadvantage, marginalization, and discrimination) that disability theorists, researchers, and activists have produced. Perhaps, in the future, you would even be motivated to run some experiments on the relation between exposure to philosophy of disability/disability theory/disability activism and incorporation of disabled identity. I would be delighted to embark on such studies with you.
Posted by: Shelley | 06/16/2016 at 10:29 AM
Hi Josh,
You're correct about my own view. In short, I think that the true self is deeply related to endorsement from the perspective of one's values. But I have come to think that what constitutes one's values is quite a bit more complicated than what it is often thought to be--i.e., one's values are not identical to one's value judgments. And I'm also coming to think that what constitutes endorsement is probably a bit more complicated than it is sometimes made out to be. But I still think that the notion of the true self is deeply related to and profitably understood in terms of reflective endorsement.
I must admit that I wasn't appreciating exactly how the work you've been discussing here shows that our notion of the true self is divorced from reflection and endorsement. It seems that your work suggests that our judgments about another person's true self do not track our assessment of their own sense of what they endorse--i.e., Mark may claim that he endorses homophobia, but one might judge, instead, that his true self holds that homosexuality is morally acceptable. One explanation of this may be that our judgments about the true self track *our own* endorsements, even when they are judgments about another person's true self. This seems to me to be one reading of the results you've obtained. But please correct me if I'm mistaken here. Another explanation may be that our judgments about the true self track what we take to be the correct endorsement--where this may come apart from an individual's explicit endorsement. This seems to me to be suggested by the predicted intuitions I was describing in my comments. It also seems consistent with the result you've obtained. Again, please let me know if you think otherwise.
So, in the end, I don't yet see that people's reactions to these scenarios show that judgments about the true self are divorced from endorsement, or even reflection. I guess I think that there are explanations of the intuitions under discussion that are compatible with reflective endorsement views, albeit ones that are more nuanced than, say, Frankfurt's view. But I would be very interested to hear what you think.
Posted by: Ben M-Y | 06/16/2016 at 10:37 AM
Hi Ben,
This idea sounds very intriguing, and I want to hear more. I think we probably both agree that there is some superficial sense in which cases like the ones we have been discussing speak against the reflection-based view. (At least on an initial inspection, it seems like the part of the self that counts in these cases as the agent's true self is not the reflective part but rather the more emotional, appetitive part.) But if I understand correctly, you are thinking that this more superficial reading of the situation is mistaken. Could you say more about what you think is actually going on here?
Hi Shelley,
Thanks for writing! I really appreciate everything you've done to draw attention to issues about disability in our discipline, and also to facilitate research on questions in the philosophy of disability. I completely agree that there is a huge amount of potential for work at the intersection of experimental philosophy and disability theory.
I don't have any background in disability theory myself, so I feel like it would be a bit presumptuous of me to comment on the difficult philosophical questions that arise in that area. However, I am excited to see that some people who do have a serious background in disability theory have begun using the method of experimental philosophy (e.g., in the work of Steve Steward). It will be really interesting to see how research at this intersection continues to develop.
Posted by: Joshua Knobe | 06/16/2016 at 01:13 PM
Josh, thanks for your kind remarks about my work in philosophy of disability and my other endeavours.
I want to take this opportunity to remind readers/listeners of the Discrimination and Disadvantage blog that the blog now has a Facebook group page where additional items are shared and posted, and on which discussion ensues. Like the blog itself, the Discrimination and Disadvantage Facebook group focuses on issues of disadvantage, oppression, exclusion, social justice, etc. within academia, especially issues that concern philosophers, but issues of social justice, oppression, exploitation, etc. more generally are also highlighted.
To join the D & D Facebook group, just click on the words "Our Facebook Page" at the top right of the screen here.
Posted by: Shelley | 06/16/2016 at 02:38 PM
Josh,
I get the feeling that there is a contradiction or at least a tension between what you want to claim in regards to addiction and what you have said in response to Jesse’s remarks about (so-called) “mental illness”. I think my concern picks up on some aspects of your remarks that Jesse noticed, though he can correct me if I have misinterpreted him.
On the one hand, you want to claim that when people refrain from addictive drug use, they have acted in accordance with their true selves. On the other hand, you seem to think that people diagnosed as mentally ill are not true to themselves if they identify with their “mental illness” and thereby do not readily avail themselves to “treatment.”
For many (if not most) people who have been diagnosed (psychiatrized) as mentally ill, treatment amounts to large doses of addictive drugs. Many people who are labelled with psychiatric conditions repeatedly “go off their meds.” Among other reasons for doing so, many of these people feel that the drugs render them unable to “be themselves,” who they really are. If I understood you correctly, you think that they would not really “be themselves” if they were to refuse to be medicated (as you put it, they “cherish their pain” which is a “barrier to treatment”).
So, we seem to have a conflicted distinction: on the one hand, some users of drugs are true to themselves when they do not use; and on the other hand, other users of drugs are true to themselves if they do use.
What seems to be at the root of this conflict is the epistemological and ontological status of mental illness. If one assumes (as I do) that (what gets called) mental illness is socially constituted, an artifact of disabling administrative, medical, and juridical discourses, then, one is inclined to say that the distinction between which users of drugs are true to themselves when they are using and which users are not true to themselves when they use is also artifactual, a matter of what is authoritatively and more generally socially permissible.
My apologies if I’ve misunderstood you, Josh. I have really enjoyed the discussion thus far.
Posted by: Shelley | 06/17/2016 at 09:19 AM
Hi Shelley,
Thanks for this further comment. Looking back, I can certainly see how my earlier comment might be reasonably construed as taking a position on the use of medication in psychiatry, but I had actually not been intending to take any position on those complex issues.
I was trying to advance the hypothesis that people's decisions about whether to seek treatment (either psychotherapy or medication) can be influenced by intuitions about whether the emotions they are experiencing are reflective of their true selves. There is of course a deeply important normative question here about whether people actually *should* seek such treatment (and if so, whether they should opt for psychotherapy or medication), but I would not be even remotely qualified to express an opinion on that question and was not intending to do so.
That said, I would obviously be happy to hear your thoughts on that question and would also be interested in hearing from others who have expertise in this area.
Posted by: Joshua Knobe | 06/17/2016 at 10:10 PM
hi Josh,
thanks for your response to my recent comment. I think that we are in agreement on more than it appears, but that we have stated our ideas in different ways, with a different emphasis. Consider this remark in your most recent comment:
"I was trying to advance the hypothesis that people's decisions about whether to seek treatment (either psychotherapy or medication) can be influenced by intuitions about whether the emotions they are experiencing are reflective of their true selves."
I think that this remark aligns with my claim that at the root of people's beliefs (and here I include philosopher's claims) about their true selves with respect to mental illness are assumptions about what mental illness is (its ontological status). In my view, any position on the normative question to which you refer will also be a position on the question of what mental illness (and impairment more generally) is and constitutive of the objects it claims to merely identify and describe.
Maybe you think that my approach relies too much on conceptual analysis. I'd be interested to know if you do. My research strategy (as Jesse and others know) has been to identify how normative positions on impairment and prenatal testing, stem cell research, etc. have contributed to the constitution of the very object about which they prescribe.
Addendum: Josh, let me add this. In my view, my approach/research strategy follows from my understanding of how power operates: in brief, that power is productive of the objects that it subsequently coerces and controls.
Posted by: Shelley | 06/18/2016 at 10:03 AM
Hi Shelley,
I apologize for not engaging more directly with the questions you are posing here. Please believe me when I say that my reticence does not involve any kind of implicit disapproval of the approach you are taking. Rather, it is simply that you are asking about topics (disability studies, psychopharmacology) in which I really have no background at all.
As a result, I would be interested in learning about those topics from you or from others with the relevant expertise, but I am very reluctant to offer any opinions of my own.
Posted by: Joshua Knobe | 06/18/2016 at 01:49 PM
Josh
not to worry. I wasn't expecting answers about the research itself of the approach, but rather thought you might have an observation to make about general "methodology" of the approach.
In any case, I think that I've got a better idea of what you meant in your response to Jesse. I'm sure he could make additional valuable contributions to a discussion about the social constitution of mental illness, as could Andrea Nicki who did a powerful interview with me in January that can be found here: http://philosophycommons.typepad.com/disability_and_disadvanta/2016/01/hello-im-shelley-tremain-and-id-like-to-welcome-you-to-the-tenth-installment-of-dialogues-on-disability-a-series-of.html
Posted by: Shelley | 06/18/2016 at 02:19 PM